Euthanasia Should Not Be Legalized Philosophy Essay.


No, euthanasia is not murder. It is an entirely new medico-legal decision made by the patient to die, to get free from the never-ending illness he or she is suffering. In the conclusion of euthanasia, the patient has informed consent, which informs about the patient's will and protects the doctor. The doctor plays just a short role in eliminating the patient’s pain.
As of February 2020, the legislative body in Spain is engaged in discussions regarding a proposed bill aimed at legalizing euthanasia and assisted suicide, while parallel legislative efforts are underway in Portugal, spurred by the endorsement of related proposals by its parliament. In New Zealand, the parliament expressed its support for the legalization of euthanasia in late 2019, with a national referendum scheduled to occur in September 2020 to further address this matter. Although it is a patient choice to live or die, in some countries, it is illegal, and some have legalized it. Many debates on legalizing it have been ongoing. But few countries accept it with statements of law under it. The countries that have legalized euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide are: In addition to this, euthanasia can be classified as active (resulting from a deliberate action) or passive (allowing someone to pass away by either stopping or not starting treatment). Euthanasia, also known as physician-assisted suicide, is the deliberate act of a doctor ending a patient's life, typically to eliminate their suffering. This practice is carried out at the request of the patient, particularly those who are experiencing significant pain and illness. The process of euthanasia is complex, involving numerous legal protocols and considerations of the patient's mental capacity and wishes. Euthanasia refers to a procedure conducted by a physician at the request of the patient to end his or her life. Various factors may ultimately drive a patient to consider euthanasia. Nonetheless, the practice is fraught with legal complexities, resulting in its prohibition in many countries. One of the advantages claimed for agent-centered versions ofdeontology is that the various agency-determining variables restrictthe scope of deontological obligations in ways that lessen thepossibilities of there being conflicts of deontological duties(Anscombe 1962). In Trolley, for example, the switchman is not seen toface a conflict of two deontological duties (a duty not to kill oneworkman versus a duty not to kill five workmen); rather, if he doesnot turn the trolley he is only omitting to save the five, not causingtheir death, and if he turns the trolley he is only (redirectively)allowing the death of the one, not causing that death, so on bothsides of the balance he acts outside of the scope of deontologicalobligations (this is what makes him free to maximize goodconsequences). Still, while such conflict-reducing possibilities arereal, few think it likely that they can be sufficient to eliminateconflict entirely. Moreover, the more restrictive of scope such agencylimitations are made to be, the more they invite the kind ofmanipulation and evasion of deontology’s norms that Leo Katz calls,“avoision” (Katz 1996).

Keywords: Euthanasia, Euthanasia-debate, Passive-euthanasia..

Making her case against any law change, Ilora Finlay, a crossbench peer and palliative care physician, told the parliamentary inquiry that legalising euthanasia in Britain could result in between 5,800 and 58,000 assisted deaths a year, based on extrapolated data from countries where it is already legal. "Such demand would divert an already stretched workforce of NHS clinicians," she said.

* Passive euthanasia has been legalized in India

They are responsible for some landmark judgements in India, such as the banning of triple talaq, opening the doors of the Sabarimala and the Haji Ali shrines to women, legalising consensual homosexual relations, legalising passive euthanasia, etc.

Another common argument for euthanasia, is that suicide is legal.

Second, causings are distinguished from allowings(Woollard, 2015, 2023). In a narrow sense of the word we will herestipulate, one allows a death to occur when: (1) one’saction merely removes a defense the victim otherwise would have hadagainst death; and (2) such removal returns the victim to some morallyappropriate baseline (Kamm 1994, 1996; MacMahan 2003). Thus,mercy-killings, or euthanasia, are outside of our deontologicalobligations (and thus eligible for justification by good consequences)so long as one’s act: (1) only removes a defense against deaththat the agent herself had earlier provided, such as disconnectingmedical equipment that is keeping the patient alive when thatdisconnecting is done by the medical personnel that attached thepatient to the equipment originally; and (2) the equipment couldjustifiably have been hooked up to another patient, where it could dosome good, had the doctors known at the time of connection what theyknow at the time of disconnection.

Euthanasia and why it should be legalized

Also known as euthanasia, assisted dying is a controversial issue for legislatures worldwide, with widely cited arguments both for and against a practice that is legal in some countries while totally taboo in others.

There are two types of euthanasia, active and passive.

In contrast to consequentialist theories, deontological theories judgethe morality of choices by criteria different from the states ofaffairs those choices bring about. The most familiar forms ofdeontology, and also the forms presenting the greatest contrast toconsequentialism, hold that some choices cannot be justified by theireffects—that no matter how morally good their consequences, somechoices are morally forbidden. On such familiar deontological accountsof morality, agents cannot make certain wrongful choices even if bydoing so the number of those exact kinds of wrongful choices will beminimized (because other agents will be prevented from engaging insimilar wrongful choices). For such deontologists, what makes a choiceright is its conformity with a moral norm. Such norms are to be simplyobeyed by each moral agent; such norm-keepings are not to be maximizedby each agent. In this sense, for such deontologists, the Right issaid to have priority over the Good. If an act is not in accord withthe Right, it may not be undertaken, no matter the Good that it mightproduce (including even a Good consisting of acts in accordance withthe Right).